Essays24.com - Term Papers and Free Essays
Search

The Duty Of Bystanders To Rescue

Essay by   •  November 28, 2010  •  1,733 Words (7 Pages)  •  1,757 Views

Essay Preview: The Duty Of Bystanders To Rescue

Report this essay
Page 1 of 7

TPL 2 Research Assignment

Introduction

Traditionally the law of torts in Australia and many other common law countries (e.g. England, Canada) have been reluctant to impose upon bystanders a general duty to aid the proverbial 'baby drowning in a puddle of water,' though there have been several exceptions to the general rule which the courts have distinguished, usually where some sort of prior relationship exists between the parties. Protagonists of a 'duty to rescue' tend to base their arguments around the idea that contemporary morality demands the law impose some sort of co-ercive measure upon those who chance by others in dire straits, drawing comparisons with areas where law reflects morality, as well as examples of jurisdictions where legislation introducing a positive duty to rescue have been enforced. Antagonists to the idea of an affirmative duty to act to the benefit of others tend to stress the importance of individual liberties within democratic societies on the one hand, and highlight the problems present in setting criteria for when a duty should exist in the other. As Australian tort law attempts to adhere to the principle of restitutio and prevent the emergence of a 'culture of blame' simultaneously, the result is that there is not likely to be a single 'correct' answer, however this essay will attempt to justify the imposition of a limited duty in a manner which considers both sides of the argument.

Proximity & Foreseeability

The first hurdle that must be crossed is reasonable foreseeability, which according to the High Court in Sullivan is 'necessary but not sufficient,' however in most cases concerning rescue foreseeability is generally not an issue. To date, Australian tort law has predominantly approached the issue of a duty to render assistance by focusing on the degree of proximity between two parties. The fact that both are human beings cannot be sufficient cause for duty, as Lord Nicholls said in Stovin:

'Something more is required than being a bystander. There must be some additional reason why it is fair and reasonable that one person should be regarded as his brother's keeper and have legal obligations in that regard.'

Beyond physical proximity, common factors considered by the courts to determine whether the required level of proximity existed include reasonable foreseeability of injury, prior relationship between parties, special positions occupied by defendants, and whether the defendant owned the premises related to the peril. Though the law in general does not impose a duty, the above cases represented circumstances under which the courts felt proximity and capacity demanded a duty to be owed.

Morality & Democracy

Fundamental to the affirmative argument is contemporary morality, what today's society believes to be 'fair, just and reasonable' expectations of citizens. Central to this argument is the notion of right and wrong. One might simply argue that it is 'right' to rescue another if there is minimal inconvenience to oneself. Simple though this may sound, it unwittingly reflects the cost-benefit principle, which says that state coercion of citizens is lawful if the benefits society receives from it outweigh the costs of deprivation of individuals' liberties. Indeed this view is backed by utilitarians such as Bentham, whose philosophy strives to obtain 'the greatest happiness for the greatest number,' strengthening the obligation to rescue 'in proportion as the danger is greater for the one, and the trouble of preserving him the less for the other.' Yes, rescuers will be inconvenienced to some degree or another, but contemporary morality demands they make a small sacrifice for the benefit of all. There are however criticisms of this approach to morality, most notably the invasion upon individuals' liberties in a democratic society. Critics argue that the notion of a positive duty to act for another's benefit goes against the general principle that one is not required to act to others benefit, as hinted by Lord Hoffmann in Stovin:

'In economic terms, the efficient allocation of resources usually requires an activity should bear its own costs. If it benefits from being able to impose some of its costs on other people [namely rescuers], the market is distorted because the activity appears cheaper than it really is.'

Furthermore, it is argued that utilising the law to enforce what was originally a moral principle would interfere with people's 'positive' morality which is ordinarily seen as providing a self sufficient moral educative function . This essentially means that whereas before most people would have rescued out of a moral obligation anyway, they now rescue because they feel they are being forced to, for of fear of sanction. However this is a relatively weak argument, as supporters of a duty draw on examples of the many other areas where the law supports the moral position of society, for example laws we have in place against the harming of others is a direct reflection of society's values. However given the law does sometimes reflect morality, a distinction must nonetheless be drawn between prohibitive laws and coercive laws, as Lord Hoffmann says in Stovin, it is one thing for the law to prohibit, 'it is another thing for the law to require that a person who is doing nothing in particular' to come to the aid of another. The above moral considerations aside, a more fundamental question is how such situations under consideration morally differ from poverty in third world countries? One knows equally well that one can save a life by donating to charity as one does he can save a life by aiding a motor vehicle accident victim, so how can we possibly distinguish the situations? Supporters of a duty to rescue would raise the issue of indeterminacy here, pointing out that the burden of helping one motor accident victim is relatively small, while it would be almost impossible to aid all those affected by famine in a fair and just way. Who's to say which one child is more deserving of food than another? If the law has already recognised the moral need to protect those who do provide aid, is it not the next logical step to impose the actual duty itself?

Practical considerations and other jurisdictions

Putting aside the moral quandaries, staunch opposers of a duty often draw attention to the practical problems associated with a positive duty. First and foremost is the setting of appropriate

...

...

Download as:   txt (10.2 Kb)   pdf (123 Kb)   docx (13.2 Kb)  
Continue for 6 more pages »
Only available on Essays24.com